NIETZSCHE’S WILL TO MADNESS
Richard Schain
Sometime
during the last week of December 1888, Friedrich Nietzsche apparently fell into
complete insanity. Many causes have been put forth as to the origin of his
mental breakdown. The thesis advanced in this article is that Nietzsche himself
deliberately decided to pass over into ‘madness.’ The evidence for this
statement has been derived from his published works, his correspondence, and
his personal circumstances. Like the fate of the mad Mr. Hyde in Robert Louis
Stevenson’s novel The Strange Case of Dr.
Jekyll and Mr. Hyde, there was no road back to normality for him.
Since the previous mid-November,
Nietzsche’s letters were revealing suggestive breaks with reality and a grandiosity
that was excessive even for him. But the complete break did not seem to occur
until December 31, when he sent a letter to August Strindberg stating he meant
to have the young Emperor [of Germany] shot and that Strindberg and he must
divorce. He signed the letter Nietzsche
Caesar (KSB 8:1229, p. 567). Subsequently, during the first week of January
1889, he sent at least a dozen, and probably more, brief notes to friends,
former colleagues, and the king of Italy that had the effect of announcing his
madness. A last long letter on January 6th to Jacob Burckhardt in Basel (KSB 8:1256,
p. 577-579) caused consternation in Burckhardt and in Nietzsche’s longtime
friend Franz Overbeck who had also received a ‘mad’ note. An eminent psychiatrist
in Basel, Professor Dr. Ludwig Wille, was consulted. It was decided that Overbeck
should immediately travel to Turin to rescue Nietzsche.
When Overbeck arrived at Nietzsche’s
room on January 8th, he described the condition in which he found
Nietzsche in a letter to Peter Gast [a.k.a. Heinrich Köselitz]:
I
saw Nietzsche in a sofa corner crouched down and reading—as it turned out, the last
proof of N contra Wagner—he looked horribly
decrepit; recognizing me, he threw himself upon me and embraced me violently,
breaking into a torrent of tears, then sinking back on the sofa, twitching and
quivering. I too could hardly stand upright from the shock. Did the abyss open
before him at that moment or was he plunged in it already? The entire Fino family
was present [his landlords]. Scarcely had he started moaning and quivering
again when he was given some bromine water that stood on the table. In a
moment, he was calm again and smiling; he began to speak of the great reception
that was prepared for the evening. So he was in the grip of delusional ideas
that never left while I was with him. He broke forth into loud singing and
frenzied piano playing, fragments from the mental world in which he had been
recently living and interspersed with indescribably uttered expressions,
sublime, wonderfully insightful and unspeakably horrible things about himself
as a successor to a dead God, all punctuated by chords from the piano after
which convulsions and outbursts of unspeakable suffering followed… . (Verrecchia
1986, 255)
There were a few details Overbeck
left out of his letter to Peter Gast. It appears that Nietzsche danced naked in
the room, evoking the antique customs of holy sexual frenzies (Verrecchia 1986,
265). It left no doubt in Overbeck’s mind that his friend had suffered a
complete mental breakdown. He arranged to have him brought back to Basel
immediately. In Basel, Nietzsche was quickly admitted to the Basel Psychiatric
Clinic headed by Dr. Wille. The diagnosis made was ‘Progressive paralysis’
(general paresis), a common diagnosis of that era in mental institutions. In
1888, there was already a suspicion that Progressive paralysis was a late
manifestation of syphilis. In 1902, when Nietzsche had become famous (he died
in 1900), a monograph was published by the noted neurologist Paul Möbius in
which was revealed for the first time to the public that Nietzsche suffered
with general paresis, a syphilitic disease of the brain resulting in insanity. From
that point on, general medical opinion was that Nietzsche had suffered with
late onset syphilis, a brain degeneration associated with agitation alternating
with euphoria and emotional instability, symptoms that Nietzsche had frequently
exhibited. The only question was whether or not his disease had affected his
philosophical activity. Opinions varied on this subject.
However, there were doubts often expressed
about the validity of the diagnosis (Schain 2001, chapt. 10). The course of
Nietzsche’s illness was not typical with the usual course of general paresis. This
diagnosis had become in the nineteenth century a common ‘wastepaper basket’
diagnosis applied to many individuals with uncertain neuropsychiatric disease.
With the advent of the laboratory diagnosis of syphilis, the number of
diagnosed cases dropped precipitously. Other causes have been offered to
explain Nietzsche’s breakdown—drugs (his sister’s explanation), cerebrovascular
disease with occult strokes, schizophrenia, manic-depressive psychosis,
fronto-temporal (brain) degeneration, and even Lyme’s disease. None of these
proposals have had enough evidence to receive general acceptance.
There are cogent reasons to believe
that Nietzsche’s ‘madness’ was not due to any exogenous agent nor to any
intrinsic mental disorder, but was a willed
act on his part. Many indications in his history and writings suggest that
this is what happened. In one of his earliest published books, Morgenröte (1881), written after resigning his professorship at Basel, the following
passages can be found under the label Significance
of madness in the history of morality:
Nevertheless,
when I say new and deviant ideas, values, desires again and again broke out,
these occurred with a fearful accompaniment: almost everywhere it was madness
that paved the way for the new ideas, that broke the spell of honored usage and
superstition.
Later
in the same passage,
Ach, so give me madness, you
heavenly powers! Madness, so that I can finally believe in myself! Give
delirium and convulsions, sudden lights and darkness, terrify me with frost and
heat, as no mortal has ever felt, with roars and prowling forms, let me howl
and whimper and creep like an animal; so only that I may find faith in myself! Doubt
consumes me, I have killed the Law; the Law frightens me as a corpse does a
living person: if I am not more than
the Law, then I am the most depraved of all. (KSA 3:14)
One
wonders if this is a script for what followed seven years later in Nietzsche’s
life.
Nietzsche’s
next book, Die Fröhliche Wissenschaft (1882), has a passage in the same vein but
more depressing, in spite of the title of the book:
Homo poeta—I myself, having made this tragedy
of tragedies entirely on my own; I who have first tied up the knot of morality
so tightly that only a God could loosen it—as Horace demanded!—I myself have
murdered all the Gods in the fourth act—from Morality! What is now to become of
the fifth? Where to get the tragic solution? Must I begin to think about a
comic solution? (KSA 3:153)
Podach (1931,
157) suggests that Nietzsche found this solution in a passage from Beyond Good and Evil:
—In
any case, with such a wish, it is necessary to be clear what one will get to
see: only a satyr’s game, only a farcical epilogue, only the ongoing proof that
the long real tragedy is at an end:
assuming that every philosophy in its development was a long tragedy. (KSA
5:25)
The
final passage I shall quote from Nietzsche’s published works—although there are
others—is from Jenseits von Gut und Böse (1886)
and exhibits his mood of extreme pessimism:
The
depravity, the destruction of higher men, of alienated souls is the rule; it is
frightening to have such a rule always before one’s eyes. The many-sided
torment of the psychologist who has discovered this destruction, the entire
inner “hopelessness” of higher men, this eternal ‘too late!’ in every sense, at
first and then almost always again discovered throughout history—can one day
embitter him, turn him against his own lot and lead him toward his own
destruction—so that he himself becomes “depraved.” (KSA 5:269)
One can
find other forms of evidence of his inclination toward madness in his
correspondence at the end of December and the first week of January. A clue as
to his intentions can be found in the letter to Peter Gast on Dec. 16 that is
concerned with his publications. In the middle of the letter, he abruptly
remarks: “Every so often I think why should I accelerate too much the tragic catastrophe of my life, which
begins with Ecce” (KSB: 1192). But
Nietzsche must have changed his mind because in a letter to Gast dated Dec. 31,
Nietzsche wrote, “Ah friend! What a moment—when your card arrived, what had I done then…It was the famous
Rubicon—I don’t know my address any longer: we can assume that it should be the
Palazzo del Quirinale” [Italian official residence in Rome] (KSB:1228).
This is a most significant statement.
The Rubicon was the fateful river in Italy across which Julius Caesar led his
legion to eventually become Emperor. It has come to signify a point of no
return for the one who crosses it. Nietzsche identified with Caesar and signed
a letter to Strindberg, “Nietzsche Caesar.” We are entitled to assume that the
Rubicon for Nietzsche meant the crossing over into madness, into a break with
reality as societies of human beings consider it to be. Nietzsche never wrote
anything that was without meaning for his own life.
August Strindberg was the individual
in Europe perhaps most capable of understanding Nietzsche at this time. Like
Nietzsche, he was a brilliant and multifaceted writer. He had just gone through
a severe episode of mental illness himself, which he had utilized to write two
of his most interesting books. The two admired each other’s works and Nietzsche
had asked him to translate Ecce Homo
into French—which Strindberg declined, citing financial needs that Nietzsche
could not possibly meet.
When Strindberg received one of
Nietzsche’s ‘madness’ notes, he immediately understood its significance. He replied
in kind with both a Greek and a Latin quotation: “Carissime doctor! qelw, qelw manhnai!” (Anacreon), meaning “I will, I will be mad!” A
quote from the Latin poet Horace follows: “Better wilt thou live, Licinus, by
neither always pressing out to sea nor too closely hugging the dangerous shore
in cautious fear of storms.” A phrase from Strindberg in Latin follows:
“Meanwhile it is a joy to be mad!” Strindberg’s reply and translations from the
Latin are found in Middleton (1969, 344-45). But Nietzsche did not follow
Horace’s (and Strindberg’s) advice. What may have been initially ‘simulation’
of madness eventually became a fixed condition in which there was no way back
to ‘normal’ life.
It is revealing to note that during the
first week of January 1889 when Nietzsche was sending out his madness notes, he
sent several notes to his publisher C. G. Naumann in Leipzig (KSB, 8:1233,1236,1237).
These are brief, to the point, and without any trace of madness. They give
directions to publish Ecce Homo immediately,
prior to Nietzsche contra Wagner, and
to return the two poems that were to end it. “Forward with Ecce!” Nietzsche wrote. Herr Gast was to be notified of the change
of plans. Tellingly, he ends the last note, “Address as usual, Turin.” Two days
before, in his letter to Peter Gast about crossing the Rubicon, he had said he
no longer knew his address, it might be the Palazzo del Quirinale. In the midst
of sending out his ‘mad’ notes, Nietzsche was obviously at this point capable
of writing a perfectly sane one if he wished to do so.
Soon after his arrival in Basel, Nietzsche
was transferred to the Psychiatric Clinic in Jena in order to be near his
mother’s home (although she was allowed to see him only occasionally). He was
under the care of Otto Binswanger, a prominent neuropsychiatrist and specialist
in the pathology of neurosyphilis. He remained in the Clinic [hospital] for
fourteen months. During this period the hospital records, given in detail by
Podach (1931, chapts. 5, 6), indicate he was noisy, often violent, incoherent,
apparently in a fully delusional state.
Shortly after admission to the Jena
Clinic, Nietzsche was visited by Peter Gast who did not think he looked too
bad. In a letter to their mutual friend Carl Fuchs, he wrote he had seen
Nietzsche in a state that “seemed to him—horrible to say—as though he were only
pretending to be insane, as though he were glad to have ended this way.” He
believed Nietzsche “would be just about as grateful to his rescuers as somebody
who has jumped into the water to drown himself and has been pulled out by some
fool of a coastguard” (Podach 1931, 214). Overbeck expressed a similar view in
a later publication, “I cannot escape the horrible suspicion that arises within
me at certain definite periods of observation, or at least at certain moments,
namely, that his madness is simulated. This impression can only be explained by
the general experience which I have had of Nietzsche’s self-concealment, of his
spiritual masks. But here, too, I have bowed to facts which over-rule all personal
thoughts and speculations” (Podach 1931, 215). But what Overbeck thought were
facts are questionable.
Nietzsche was released to the care
of his mother in March 1890. He lived for ten more years. Initially, he was
able to take long walks with his mother but at times exhibited outbursts of
rage. One thing he was able to do from his former life is to improvise on the
piano. But gradually he sunk into apathy and became bed-ridden. Some visitors
who saw Nietzsche commented on the strange ‘aura’ that seemed to surround him. In
August 1900 he developed a cold that progressed into pneumonia. He died August
25, 1900 six weeks short of his 56th birthday. Strangely, no autopsy
was performed in spite of the many questions about the cause of his breakdown—and
even though his physician Dr. Binswanger was an authority on pathology of the
brain.
Elizabeth Nietzsche, his sister,
staged an elaborate funeral. Many pretentious ‘unNietzschean’ things were said
at the ceremonies, which were long drawn-out affairs (Peters 1977, 171-74; Janz
1995, vol. 3, 352-358). A more appropriate, brief epitaph would have been that
given for Hamlet by Horatio in Shakespeare’s play. Hamlet was Nietzsche’s
favorite literary character, who by his resort to masks, buffoonery, and
suicide might be considered the later Nietzsche’s alter ego:
“Now cracks a noble heart. Goodnight,
sweet prince,
And flights of angels sing thee to thy rest!”
Nietzsche was a virtual unknown at
the time of his breakdown, except to a few individuals outside of Germany. But
soon after his admission to the mental institutions, the German press reported
about a philosopher who had gone mad and was institutionalized. Interest in
Nietzsche and his writings began to develop. Like a match applied to a woodpile,
Nietzsche’s fame began to blaze up in Germany and then elsewhere in Europe. The
adroit publicity generated by his sister who acquired his literary estate no
doubt hastened the process. By the time of his death, he was a celebrity
figure. It has been reported that German soldiers during the First World War
carried copies of Thus Spoke Zarathustra
in their knapsacks. All this happened while Nietzsche himself sunk into
deepening apathy and was incapable of becoming aware of his fame. This perhaps was
the most poignant tragedy of his life.
Over a century after his death, it
is impossible to state with absolute certainty the cause of Nietzsche’s mental
breakdown. Perhaps it is not even that important since it is his writings, not
his persona, that have had a profound effect on world letters. But people want
to know about the lives of writers who have stimulated them to new dimensions
of thought. Without Nietzsche’s madness, it is very possible that Nietzsche and
his writings would have sunk into oblivion or been reduced to a few footnotes
in scholarly tracts. There were certainly contributory factors to his breakdown,
whatever the primary cause might have been. At that time, Nietzsche lived alone
in cramped circumstances (one rented room), he had no friends or relatives
nearby, he had a very imperfect knowledge of the language of the country in
which he lived. His Basel pension was being reduced and his books did not sell;
he had to pay to have his writings published. He was probably, as he said of himself,
three-quarters blind. All these factors must have weighed on him (in spite of
his protestations to the contrary) and must have contributed to the temptation
to drop out from the ‘normal’ world, although he may not have been fully aware
how destructive the long-term consequences were to be for him.
Perhaps even more relevant was the presence
of an unconscious awareness that he, the preacher of the Übermensch, of the
will to power, of the dominance of the instincts, was, after all, just a meek
little near-blind German philosopher to whom nobody paid any attention. His few
clumsy attempts at sexual relationships had been dismal failures. What if he
was a unique prose stylist with the German language? What if he had a few isolated
readers far away? The German intellectuals had ignored or made fun of him. He
had rejected metaphysics so that no God could help him. Zarathustra was a
figment of his imagination, not a reality. As a classical philologist, he had
long known of Plato’s belief that madness for philosophers was superior to a
normal mind (Phaedrus) and Nietzsche
repeatedly dwelled on the subject in his books. The desire to assert himself through madness must have been very great. For all these
reasons and the ones discussed above, it is the judgment of this writer that
Nietzsche deliberately willed himself into a state of madness. He finally
crossed his Rubicon.
The question may arise whether any
person is able to will himself into a state of permanent madness, not merely
into a transient frenzy or temporary loss of contact with the ‘real’ world. The
conventional current psychiatric view is that unknown origin chronic psychoses
(‘madness’) such as schizophrenia or bipolar disease are due to an abnormal
brain physiology that involuntarily
affects a person’s mind. Just ‘willing’ oneself into lifelong madness is not ordinarily
regarded as a possible clinical phenomenon. However, Nietzsche was not an
ordinary person. The psychiatrist-philosopher Karl Jaspers who published a thick
tome about him (Nietzsche: Introduction
to the Understanding of his Philosophical Activity) commented there was
only one Nietzsche and there will never be another like him. Anything could be
possible for the unique individual that was Friedrich Nietzsche.
The
translations into English in this essay, if not otherwise stated, are by the
author.
References:
Janz, Curt Paul. Friedrich Nietzsche Biographie. Munich:
Carl Hanser, 1993.
Middleton, Christopher. Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1969.
Peters, Heinz F. Zarathustra’s
Sister. New York: Markus Wiener, 1977.
Podach,
Erich. F. (1931): The Madness of
Nietzsche. London: Putnam, 1931. (Translated by F.A.Voigt from Nietzsche’s Zusammenbruch.
Heidelberg: Kampmann, 1930.) The copious references and notes in the original German
edition unfortunately were left out of the English translation.)
Schain, Richard. The Legend of Nietzsche’s Syphilis.
Westport: Greenwood Press, 2001.
Verrecchia,
Anacleto. Zarathustra’s Ende. Vienna:
Böhlaus, 1986. (German translation of La Catastrofe
di Nietzsche a Torino, 1976)
Published in: The Agonist: A Nietzsche
Circle Journal, Vol. XII, 2019.