THE NECESSITY FOR
ESCHATOLOGY
Richard Schain
Eschatology
– The striving of humans toward eternity
I
The
preoccupations of philosophers are rarely shared by non-philosophers. The
nature of truth, of reality, of knowledge; the distinction between appearance
and essence, self and the universe, being and nothingness—all these
traditional problems with which philosophers have wrestled through the
centuries are of little interest to most individuals, whether little or highly
educated. This is perhaps one reason why metaphysics, which historically has
been a significant part of philosophy in western culture, has been replaced by
phenomenology, commonly regarded as ÒscientificÓ philosophy. The direction was
set by Kant who insisted metaphysics must be scientific. One can hardly say
that this has resulted in any increase of interest in philosophy among the
general population. It has led, however, to a certain Selbsthass among philosophers, causing Leszek
Kolakowski to say in his entertaining essay Metaphysical Horror (2001) that Òfor well over a hundred
years, a large part of academic philosophy has been devoted to the business of
explaining that philosophy is either impossible or useless or both.Ó
Nevertheless,
there is another point of view. It is that metaphysics is indispensable to the
human condition. To return again to Kant, he asserts in his Prolegomena to
any Future Metaphysics
that, in spite of the difficulties (notably posed by his own major opus on the
subject), it is as little to be expected that human beings will give up
metaphysics as they will give up breathing! Western history has borne out the
correctness of KantÕs prediction. It is worth quoting at length from the
prologue of Mauricio Beuchot to La Metafisica como Necesidad (1994), a scholarly monograph by Kuri Camacho
(my translation):
ÒÉwe confront a negation greater than metaphysics has ever known.
Throughout history, many have decreed its death: the skeptics, the Epicureans,
the nominalists, the empiricists, the epigones of Kant, the positivists, and
now one sees, not a frank discarding of metaphysics as announced by Carnap, but
what was espoused [its disparagement] by the later Heidegger, and in a certain
manner, the later Wittgenstein. But metaphysics always has returned to have its
fueros.Ó
It is revealing
that Beuchot uses the term fueros
or ÒprivilegesÓ to describe the place of metaphysics. The term refers to
special rights, notably those enjoyed by the Roman Catholic Church in Hispanic
societies. There can be little doubt that metaphysics found a congenial home in
the dogmas of institutionalized religions and this association continues to the
present day. With the exception of minor islands such as New England
transcendentalism – long disappeared except in history books – the
metaphysical aspirations of European-descent peoples have been met through
theistic religions. Christianity has always been jealous of its fueros in the area of metaphysics. In earlier
centuries, one would face the stake by expressing metaphysical ideas outside
the established churches; today one merely has to accept the role of an
eccentric, ignored by the doctors of the churches and the universities alike.
How is one to
reconcile the apparently contradictory observations that the metaphysical
questions are of no interest to most persons with the evident persistence of
metaphysics in religion as still a fundamental ingredient of society? I submit
that the metaphysical questions enumerated in the opening paragraph above are
not the questions that concern individuals outside of academia, where the
admonition of Kant to make metaphysics scientific has never been forgotten. To
succinctly jargonize the matter, it is eschatology, not ontology or epistemology that
interests the thoughtful individual. The non-philosopher has only a vague
interest in the abstractions of universal ideas, what he really wants is to
apprehend the meaning of his own life. This inevitably becomes a matter of
eschatology.
II
The essential
problem of philosophy for the thinking individual, homo sapiens, has to do with the meaning of his own
life. All the other metaphysical questions are significant only to
professionals of philosophy who are concerned with its history and certain of
its ideas from the past that have become revered traditions. But concern with
the meaning of oneÕs own life – not human life as an abstraction - is an
intuitive concern for every reflective person, testifying to the depth of his
mind. Every reflective person wants his life to be significant; his problem is
how this is to be accomplished. This is the principal task of the conscious
mind. I use the term mind
in the sense of Geist
in German, inclusive of mind, spirit, self, intellect – not merely as a
describer of adaptive activity. Without a sense of the metaphysics of mind, one
cannot deal with this issue other than in a spiritless and uninteresting
manner.
The Xenophontine
Socrates is said in the Memorabilia
to have summed up his approach to life as follows: ÒI am growing in goodness
and I am making better friends. And that I may say, is my constant thought.Ó
Plato in Phaedo and The
Republic has Socrates
dwelling on eschatology in the form of myth-making. How could it be otherwise
since what would be the point of growing in goodness if it did not possess some
ultimate meaning? The later rejection of eschatology probably weakened Greek
philosophy and paved the way for the spread of Christianity in the antique
world. The approach attributed to the founding father of the schools of Athens
should have been taken more seriously by his epigones and by later European
philosophers. Perhaps Plato himself, with his fertile imagination, introduced
too many irrelevancies into philosophy.
If western
philosophy gradually lost interest in eschatology, this was not true of western
religion. The foundation of Christianity is the idea that aligning oneself with
Christian belief is aligning oneself with God; the consequence is the winning
of eternal life. The details of this alignment and the nature of the eternal
life has been interpreted differently throughout the history of Christian
churches, but the basic eschatology is the same – believe and you will
find salvation. The success of Christianity is based on the appeal of its
eschatological doctrines. Believers find meaning in their lives. A similar
story can be told about the successes of Islam.
It is hard to
question the evidence that the need for an ultimate meaning in oneÕs life, i.e
the necessity for eschatology, is why religion still exists in an age of
science. Science does not provide meaning. However, a rational person cannot
believe anything, no matter how seductive the belief, without the ability to be
able to incorporate it into oneÕs rationally organized experience of the world.
The dictum that what is impossible for man is possible for God has lost its
persuasive power in the age of science. We are fated to think, as D.R. Kashaba
puts it in his stirring writing Let Us Philosophize (1998), and one form of thought is the
emergence of an intellectual conscience. This is what Kant must have meant by
his appeal for a ÒscientificÓ metaphysics. For him, wissenschaftlich meant rational, coherent, capable of
fitting into knowledge as a whole. Every age seems to create its own
eschatology, reflecting its own mental evolution. Simple minds have always
needed a simple eschatology. Christianity, in spite of the prodigious labors of
some of its theologians to convert dogmas into symbols, rests fundamentally on
a simple, almost embarrassingly na•ve belief structure. There is an absolute requirement
for faith and little demand is made on the intellectual conscience. On the
basis of the experience of his descent from generations of Lutheran pastors,
Nietzsche concluded that faith is cowardice.
Things were
supposed to be different in the new age of science. In the first part of the
nineteenth century, Auguste Comte worked out his celebrated Òlaw of three
stagesÓ in which the human mind first turns to theology (fiction), then to
metaphysics (abstraction), and finally to science (positivism). It has not
worked out that way. The majority of the western world has not gotten past
stage one. This is because, as I believe, there have been no meaningful
eschatologies evolved for stages two and three. Science explains how things
work but not their meaning. The absurdity of life looms as the inevitable
consequence of a mind without an eschatology.
It is not quite
accurate to say that there have been no competitors at all to religion in the
domain of eschatology. If eternity is not held out as a possibility, then
aligning oneÕs Geist with
movements extending it in time or space is perhaps not an unreasonable
alternative. Thus one may align himself with societal
movements—nationalism, socialism, communism, racial or ethnic
identifications, even humanity as a whole, any plausible movement that allows
one to feel his life has a meaning beyond the limitations of his own being.
Hitler and his followers were willing to forego Christian salvation for the
sake of a thousand year Aryan Reich in which the social compact was not
extended to non-Aryans. It was notorious that committed communist ideologues
did not feel the need for religion. However, in time, most societal ideologies
break down and are no longer significant substitutes for metaphysical meaning.
A weak substitute
for a vital eschatology is the biological one in which the solution to the
problem of the meaning of life is found through procreation papered over by
handing down ancestral traditions. This is patently absurd, for how can meaning
in life be achieved by merely propagating it? One cannot foist oneÕs own
metaphysical responsibilities onto his or her children. They then do the same.
This basically reduces one to an animal state where the instinct for
procreation reigns supreme. A very limited intellectual perspective is required
for the biological answer to be completely effective.
III
Every age
requires the formulation of eschatological concepts reflecting its intellectual
development. Eschatology is not dogma, but the individualÕs intuition of the
eternality of his existence. Even physics is not a reproduction of reality
according to Niels Bohr (quoted by Kolakowski), but rather a schematization of
experience, performed with the aid of artificially constructed instruments. So
it is with eschatology except that the experience is of the life of the mind
rather than that derived from technology. It is the subjective self instead of
the object world that is the teacher. The conception is similar to that
expressed by Socrates in Phaedo
when he says that no man of sense should expect the story he had just related
about the journey of the soul be exactly as he had told it. But Socrates
thought one may venture to believe that something of the kind is true.
No contemporary
man of sense should imagine that the picture of reality obtained through
scientific study could be completely or even mainly true. It is a useful scheme
for mastering nature and surviving a threatening world but it can hardly
reflect the full reality of homo sapiens. The accumulated intuitions of mankind
indicate a reality transcending physical nature. However, concepts that purport
to reflect the human condition must conform to reality in all its forms to the
extent they are known. Metaphysics cannot exclude the physical world from its purview.
Descartes, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, Bergson, and Teilhard de Chardin knew that
and their philosophies were enriched. That they may have gone astray at times
with their science is beside the point.
An individual
searching for eternity cannot afford to ignore the discoveries of modern
physics about the nature of time. In general, the deductions of Kant about the
mind forming perceptual schemata (the a priori forms) have been shown to be remarkably
prescient. Beyond KantÕs simple schemata, Einsteinian relativity radically
altered the concept of time in the twentieth century. That development is often
compared to the Copernican revolution on notions about the universe and manÕs
place in it. No longer can time be considered as an absolute stretching back into
the past and forward into the future at any moment called Ònow.Ó Time is
relative, a function of the state of the various objects existing in the
universe. This must affect concepts of eschatology that are predicated on an
ÒendÓ of time. But time does not end because it does not have a beginning,
there are only different points on an infinite continuum representing the
ÒnowsÓ of all possible observers. The physicist Bryant Greene points out that
it is better to imagine time as a continuous block of ice than as a flowing
river (The Fabric of the Cosmos, 2004).
This is a
concept difficult to encompass by the mind just as it is difficult to imagine
bending of a pluridimensional space. The human mind is constructed to visualize
reality in a certain way as was discovered by Kant. Just as individuals had to
learn to change their intuitive perceptions that the earth is flat or that the
sun rotates around it, so one has to learn that linear time is a construct of
the mind only schematically representing reality. The emerging problem is to
rethink the notion of the Ònow.Ó What is its significance if, as Einstein has
said, the now has no place in the conception of time of modern physics. This
bears greatly on an eschatology indicating the meaning of oneÕs life.
In my book In Love with Eternity (2005), I put forth the metaphor of a pointillist
canvas of eternity referring to the concept of an Eschaton. I do not expect this metaphor to satisfy
everyone (perhaps no one) but I think individuals should strive to create their
own eschatology instead of depending on external authority figures to provide
it readymade. These traditional schemata may temporarily rouse the mind but
should only be used as points of departure. An individual is maintained in a
mentally infantile state by relying on others for the most important things.
Intellectual individuality is the hallmark of homo sapiens, however much
certain leaders of religion may preach otherwise. History should be used not
abused. In this regard, it is worth remembering NietzscheÕs view that the will
to power permeates societal institutions of every type.
IV
The Òpointillist
canvas of eternityÓ refers to a notion I have that every individual existence
can be imagined as a brush stroke in a vast canvas called eternity. Past
existences have not disappeared, they exist as a metaphysical stroke on the
canvas. What takes form in life – and I mean all life, not just human
life – determines the quality of the stroke. The unique human
consciousness of ÒnowÓ indicates awareness of the coming-into-being of an
individual life. This Ònow,Ó however, may be a peculiar human thought that is
irrelevant in the larger scheme of things. If I am asked to what end this
cosmic canvas, I have no answer and must fall back on docta ignorancia, intellectual ignorancia. If I were a
mythmaker, I might rise to the occasion, but I know my limits. I do know that a
profound sense of peace is felt when the specter of transitoriness in existence
is expunged and one can intuit a meaning to his life, albeit this meaning is
hidden from him. To those who think philosophy should be science and mysticism
is treason to it, I say like the American patriot Patrick Henry who stood up
for his convictions, ÒIf this be treason, then make the most of it.Ó
But I suggest
that the conception of a timeless canvas of eternity on which is etched the
phenomenon of individual existences is in accord with the most reasonable view
of the nature of reality and is not an imaginary idea that violates oneÕs
intellectual integrity. It is founded on an understanding of oneÕs existence
within a rational reality. As much as the need for meaning, homo sapiens has a
need for rationality in his conceptions. Beliefs must fit into a total
experience of reality. On this is founded Kantian critique. One may despair of
rationality amidst the bizarre beliefs that motivate people; still, it is an
ideal to be sought after.
The most
important thing of all, Nietzsche said, is that we think well of ourselves. How
can one think well of himself, however, when he learns that he is a speck of
sand in the limitless expanse of the cosmos, destined to exist no more than a
nanosecond in the infinity of time? It is this sense of meaninglessness, not
the fear of death that underlies the Angst of Kierkegaard, the Sorge of Heidegger, the absurditŽ of Camus and the horror metaphysicus of Kolakowski. How can a thinking being
not be depressed by the thought of the transitoriness of his being? It is
impossible for a serious person to ultimately be content with his meaningless
miniscule movements within society. There must be something more in order that
cynicism and ennui not be the final victor in human life. But if an individual
is capable of angst, then he is capable of discovering more in life than what a
technology-burdened society has taught him.
A human being
wants to make something meaningful of his own life. The thought that his
individual development has no significance in the scheme of things is what
drives him to sacrifice himself on the altars of dubious causes. The brilliant
Portuguese writer Fernando Pessoa, whose horizons of thought went beyond most
individuals, said that his own development was the most he could accomplish in
his lifetime and that he could not really know, much less provide, what was needed
by other individuals. This is heresy in a culture dominated (albeit
hypocritically) by values of the social good. But Pessoa more than most is a
vibrant part of the canvas of eternity. It was to be expected that his life
within society was beset with difficulties. The truly developed individual
usually dies young.
There are those
who say they find their meaning in life from a consciousness of God. They have
been vouchsafed direct access to the source of all meaning from a church, from
holy scriptures or directly from deity itself. They claim to be the fortunate
recipients of divine grace. Those who have not received this grace can only be
envious or skeptical. That God should make himself known to some and not to
others seems to be the ultimate absurdity. Beyond that, God says different
things to different people. The religions of the east know nothing of him at
all. Perhaps, however, a divine providence moves in mysterious ways and it may
be that those who are the recipients of grace are given it because they are
incapable of finding meaning on their own. They are the ones who, unlike
Gotthold Lessing, want to be given truth rather than to search for it.
My intuition
that I have my place in the panorama of eternity strengthens me to build my
life as I think it should be built and not chase after the evanescent
gratifications that exist in all societies. This is a confession of faith, but
it is a faith based on a rational conception of reality. Writing this essay
develops my self. The purpose of philosophy, as I conceive it, is to give
direction to the spirit and not to construct spiritless theories of knowledge.
Eschatology takes precedence over epistemology. What is unanalyzable should not
be analyzed.
Richard Schain
is an independent philosopher who works as a neurologist in a California State
Hospital. His recent publications include In Love With Eternity (2005), Radical Metaphysics (2002) and The Legend of NietzscheÕs
Syphilis (2001).