The Art Form Known as Philosophy
Richard Schain
I believe the main thing to
know about philosophy is that it is an art form. Philosophy is the art of literary
expression of the realities of the universe as
perceived by the philosopher. A philosopher who has not experienced life
and the world in their many manifestations is like a composer who has never heard
music. Philosophy cannot and should not think of itself as expressing universal
‘truths’ any more than Picasso or Van Gogh expressed universal truths with
their images. Much of what goes under the name of philosophy today are efforts
at cognitive science, mathematics, history, or journalism. Philosophy is none
of these; it is an art form whose identifying characteristic is the subjective expression
of perspectives of existence that have been developed by the philosopher. It is
well known that the temperament and circumstances of life of philosophers
greatly influence their philosophy. The appreciation of philosophy requires a
taste for art that is not greatly different from that required for other art
forms. The person whose spirit is not touched at one time or another by music,
by painting, by architecture, or by poetry will not be touched by genuine
philosophy. Plato, regarded as the founder of discursive western philosophy,
was seen as a poet by the scientifically minded Aristotle.
“Everything is hateful to me which is merely instructive
without increasing or directly enlivening my activity (unmittelbar zu beleben).” With this quotation from Goethe, the
young Nietzsche began his essay entitled On
the Advantages and Disadvantages of History for Life in which he asserted
that knowledge serves the individual only insofar as it enlivens him; otherwise it is superfluous, and what is superfluous
is the enemy of a fulfilling life. I have come to think that this insight is
applicable, not only to the study of history, but to all literary pursuits, including philosophy, in which the
reader is not ‘enlivened’ but merely instructed, entertained, or otherwise
diverted. Analytic philosophy today is akin to spiders weaving their webs in
human habitations—useless to human beings, except to university faculty who
need publications for advancement or prestige. Philosophy as I understand it
arises out of the life experiences of the philosopher. Without this connection,
it is obscure verbiage.
With a little imagination, one can notice that the style
of philosophers is often similar to the style of other artists of their locale
and time. Thus British philosophy of the 17th and 18th
century resembles British landscape painting and portraiture; it is somber and
oriented toward the surface of phenomena as befits spiritless art. One could
envision Hobbes, Locke, or Hume as intellectual landscapists. French philosophers
of the Enlightenment resemble their country’s fiction writers and dramatists;
they are clever, light, and full of nuances. Voltaire and Rousseau are like
frothy cakes. The French impressionist school of art continued in this vein. In
central Europe, however, one finds philosophers in the expressionist style,
resembling artists such as Ernst Kirchner, Edvard Munch (Norwegian but worked
in Germany), or Franz Marc. The emphasis is on seriousness, depth, and
feelings. Kierkegaard and Nietzsche are the foremost examples of Expressionism
in philosophy (a better term than Existentialism); both were explicit in their
identification with art. When Kierkegaard repeatedly proclaimed in his Concluding Unscientiific Postscript that “Truth is Subjectivity,” he was
essentially stating that philosophy is art.
~ ~ ~
Philosophy is that genre of
literary artwork in which the feelings of the philosopher are transmuted linguistically into meaningful
ideas. Visual art creates images, musical art creates sound, the art of
philosophy creates ideas. The idea is the
art. Just as without feelings there is no visual art; so without feelings,
there is no philosophy; there is only logic, which is a tool of scientific
investigation. When General Sherman, referring to the American Civil War, said,
“War is hell,” he was not giving vent to simple emotion; he was engaging in a
philosophic discourse by formulating a proposition founded on his own
experiences and feelings. Its validity derives from Sherman’s hidden but
intense emotional state during the war, and can be apprehended in its entirety
only by those who have undergone similar experiences and felt similar feelings.
In this sharing of experience, feeling, and meaning lies the substance of
philosophy.
If one looks back into the origins of western philosophy
in the antique Greek world, there can be discerned the titanic effort of
individuals to become conscious of their own nature and to give meaning to
their feelings. More than any other races at the dawn of conceptual thought,
the early Greek thinkers were able to find sense in human existence without
recourse to superstition. The embodiment of the move toward a philosophical
culture is the figure of Heraclitus—in my opinion, the real father of western philosophy.
The assertions of Heraclitus that survived the destruction of antique Greek
culture define philosophy as that form of human expression centered on the
expression of feelings. “I searched into myself” is the epitome of the wisdom
of Heraclitus, expressed well before the famous statement decrying the
unexamined life that was attributed to Socrates. A similar current, more
difficult of access by westerners, began at an earlier time in the forests of
India with the composition of the Upanishads by the Vedic seers.
The most fateful development for modern philosophy has
been the emergence of Kantian-type, analytic, scholarly, university-based
‘philosophy’. The contemporary analytic philosopher of whatever ilk does not
communicate personal feelings or intuitions; he analyzes or ‘deconstructs’
language. His approach does not lead to expression of the interior self—which
he regards as mysticism and irrelevant to modern philosophy—but rather to the
invention of new ‘grammars’ of language that purport to clarify thought
processes, often expressed in mathematical terms. He is obsessed with the
analysis of language and cognition. The concepts of metaphysics developed by
Plato and set forth by Aristotle (although they did not use that term) are
consigned to the dust heap of mysticism. (The pre-Alexandrian Greek philosophers
did very well without a science of linguistics.) The philosophical breadth of a
Heraclitus or Parmenides has disappeared in post-Kantian scientific philosophy.
The influence of Husserl, Wittgenstein, Derrida, and their epigones, even more
effectively than Kant, expunged metaphysics from the purview of university
philosophy. But without metaphysics, there is no philosophy as an art form. Two
centuries of worship of scientific technology has smoothed the way for this
development. The logicians are in the saddle, riding upon contemporary
philosophical minds.
~ ~ ~
At one time, systematic
philosophy, which may be regarded as an architectural mode of philosophical
expression, was the principal form of philosophy. One can detect the
theological spirit in the works of systematizers like Spinoza, Leibniz, and
Hegel, except they are founded upon a feeling of intellectual rather than
divine revelation. The persecution of philosophers as heretics is explicable as
churches’ response to rival theologies. Churches rarely burned other types of
artists; even the New England Puritans were content to limit their punishment
of sinful artists to a day or two in the pillory. Raphael could include his
voluptuous mistress in his Transfiguration
that now hangs in the Vatican. However, the gentle Spinoza and the harmless
Descartes were menaced by their churches, and in Italy, that country’s promise
of a humanistic philosophy was brought to an end by the Roman Inquisition. Père
Teilhard de Chardin, the last European systematizer, had his enlightened
conceptions worked out in Le Phénomène
Humain suppressed by the Vatican. At the present time, systematic
philosophy has gone out of fashion, largely as a result of the loss of
reputation suffered by all non-empirical cosmologies in a scientific era.
~ ~ ~
The expropriation of the term
‘philosophy’ by academicians has been catastrophic for this high form of human expression.
Genuine philosophy as originated in the ancient Greek or Hindu world does not
exist today. There is philosophy as cognitive science, there is the form of
psychological anatomy known as phenomenology, there is philosophy expressed
through mathematical symbols, and there is, as always, the history and critique
of former philosophers that is the stock in trade of university professors in
need of academic advancement. A more recent trend is lucrative popular
philosophy that has become a commercial affair of university extensions and
other business enterprises.
The prototype modern western philosopher is a person who
writes in a scholarly manner, but also with a smooth journalistic touch. He
finds his audience within an intellectual elite who enjoy scholarly accounts of
happenings on the world’s stage. However, the world is in need of art, as Nietzsche wrote, not popular
journalists and certainly not scholarly historians. The world needs art because
it needs to experience life in newer and more profound ways than in the past. The
onslaught of technology has concealed the reality of life from contemporary
individuals. Computerized vignettes have largely replaced the old intellectual
‘feuilletons’ of newspapers. But it is through experiences that individuals
deepen the reality of their lives and it is the purpose of art to provide
experiences to those who yearn for them—for both the creative artist as well as
the auditor of art. Of all the arts that are needful to human beings, the art
of philosophy is needed most of all since it is in meaningful ideas that the
modern age is most deficient. Technology builds robots everywhere but it cannot
provide the inner life needed by living individuals; this insight was expressed
at the dawn of technology by Mary Shelley and Heinrich Heine. Concepts that
enliven one’s soul do not come mechanically from the powers of science any more
than they can be handed down by powers on high; they appear during internal
‘processing’ (for want of a better term) of meaningful experiences. The
experience of the feelings and intuitions of another human being occurs through
art; when these feelings and intuitions are intellectually expressed through
language, they are called philosophy.
~ ~ ~
Today, the independent philosopher
must have the mentality of an artist who believes in the value of ideas
objectified in literary form and that stand for his life experiences. The era
of a Socrates enchanting his listeners verbally is long over. Now the
philosopher is an alchemist who should transform written language into
experiences for the reader. His art is judged not by the fluency of his prose,
his virtuosity with language, or his gifts of imagery and metaphor. All of
these may contribute to his art but are not central to it, any more than
accuracy of representation or cleverness in composition is central to the work
of a great painter. What is central is the expression of thoughts that
represent his own realities, and thereby open the reader’s eyes and ears to
what he has not previously seen or heard—or perhaps his nose to what he had not
smelled! (á la Nietzsche). It is the task of the reader to relate to the truth
of the philosopher’s ideas, not truth as understood scientifically from the
viewpoint of acquisition of facts, but a deeper truth in which the reader experiences the ideas of the philosopher
as they represent his own unformed feelings. The successful encounter of the
artist and his auditor is much like falling in love; it is an event clothed in
mystery that is impossible to predict or insure. Goethe caught the spirit of
philosophical creativity in lines from the prologue to Faust in which the Lord is speaking to mankind:
Das Werdende, das ewig wirkt
und lebt,
umfass euch mit der Liebe
holden Schranken,
und was in schwankender
Erscheinung schwebt,
befestigt mit dauernden Gedanken!
Which I translate as:
New creation, eternally
occurring,
ye shall contain with love’s
kind attention,
and what freely floats, dimly
swaying,
surely shall ye fix with
lasting conception!
~ ~ ~
Therefore, the task of the
artist-philosopher is to express ideas that lastingly
affect his readers. He cannot rely on sound, story, rhyme, rhythm, or
visual effects to affect them; when he does so, he moves away from his role as
a philosopher. It is his ideas that are his central concern and it is their expression
that he must rely upon to accomplish his goal—affecting the interior state of
his readers.
~ ~ ~
Suzanne Langer defined
philosophy as the continual pursuit of meanings (Philosophy in a New Key); but genuine meanings, of course, can only
originate from the philosopher’s own experiences. Thus the ancient maxim,
‘first live, then philosophize.’ In his concentration on conceptualizing from
the reality of his own experiences, the philosopher is more purely an artist
than any other type of creative person since he does not honey his work with
superficial glosses. When a philosopher adulterates his work with the
attractions of poetic form, drama, or story, he may facilitate attracting an
audience, but it is at the price of loss of attention to his ideas. Who takes
seriously the ideas of Robinson Jeffers, D. H. Lawrence, Hermann Hesse, or even
Thoreau who inserted most of his profoundest thoughts into descriptions of
nature or his housekeeping? (The fate of Goethe’s ideas was unique in this
respect.) Heraclitus was on target when he wrote, “The Sibyl with raving mouth
uttering her solemn, unadorned, unperfumed words reaches out with her voice
over a thousand years.”
Philosophy is not for children any more than Rembrandt or
Beethoven is for them. It is not a question of chronological age but of
maturity of mind. The majority of people never develop their interior selves
sufficiently to be responsive to philosophic thought; for those people, there
are other art forms or if all else fails, there are the myths of religion to
provide for their needs for transcendence. Still there is an element of pathos
felt when a chronologically mature person cannot experience philosophy; it is a
form of illiteracy that suggests the need for cultural development within a
society. A large number of philosophically illiterate individuals indicates
cultural impoverishment, akin to reading illiteracy in a society. Such
societies are vulnerable to all forms of demagoguery and oppression. Without
philosophy, it is difficult to maintain one’s dignity into adult life; this may
be why philosophically illiterate societies are youth oriented.
~ ~ ~
Scientists impose control on
their surroundings through technology; artists influence their surroundings
though their art. The faith of the artist is that the feeling or thought he
expresses in his art will affect someone, even if it should be just one person.
Once this is understood, the nature of philosophy as an art form becomes clear.
The difficulty with philosophy arises when the philosopher is deluded into
thinking that he transmits universal facts instead of personal expressions. The
systematizers, analyzers, and phenomenologists do not want to be artists; they
want to be scientists. They are frustrated physicists, mathematicians, or
cognitive psychologists who try to adapt philosophy to their own purposes.
Edmond Husserl famously asserted that philosophy must be ‘strict science’.
The urge to be scientists, linguists, or psychologists,
anything but philosophers, is why philosophers have been prone to disconnect
their concepts from their human origins. One then has philosophy as natural law
or descriptive science. Somehow the ‘philosopher’ has been privileged through
his superior logic to be given universal insights into the world of reality
beyond ordinary people. Ralph Waldo Emerson said that the generalizing urge is
felt to be a manifestation of divinity in human beings; this is why a thrill is
felt upon creation of every generalization. Emerson was speaking with tongue in
cheek, but there is more to be learned from his comment than the epistemology
of logicians. Religions developed out of the desire of men to transform their
personal conceptions into eternal truths. This tendency reveals a failure of
understanding of the personal nature of conceptions and essentially a lack of
respect for the creative process. Philosophy as analytic science is the most
recent attempt to place philosophic thought on some absolute platform.
Faith in the power of art is the only faith I know that
acknowledges the capacity of human beings to themselves transcend their animal being. It is the only faith that
does not violate one’s intellectual conscience. A clear, well-founded feeling
for the place of art in human life is the best antidote to religious
superstition or scientific domination. The Socrates of the Phaedo understood philosophy—the love of wisdom—as the greatest of
the arts and rejected its
transformation into science. Plato relates how Socrates in his youth was seized
by a “prodigious desire” to know natural science. This was a stage in the
philosophical development of Socrates; later he moved on to his soul-based concept
of the role of philosophy. There will be no rebirth of philosophy in our
object-based society until this phase is again passed. There has never been any
justification for defacing this greatest of all the human arts, which has been
so fruitful in elevating the character of those who have embraced it.
~ ~ ~
The obligation of the
philosopher is to bring his spirit to life in his writings. He should not seek
to bemuse his reader through literary craftsmanship or overwhelm him with
specialized terminology. The posture of the scholarly expert is the
occupational hazard of contemporary philosophers. With rare exceptions, they
have followed the dictum of Husserl that philosophy must be strict science. On
the other hand, ‘New Age’ philosophy in America at present is often superficial
catering to gullible masses. One recalls the definition of a sophist by
Socrates as a person who makes money from his teachings. But one is no
improvement over the other. The littérateur may lull a reader into
forgetfulness of self; expertism intimidates him into thinking his own mind
cannot compare with that of the professional expert. The expert may also write
cleverly and combine craft and expertise into an overpowering witch’s brew that
extinguishes all awareness of self in a reader—an awareness that is the sine qua non of significant literary
experience.
The philosopher ought not to live in a bloodless,
abstract world (this was a fault of Emerson); neither should he be primarily
concerned with topical issues of morality or politics. Those can be left to
moralists and politicians. He must convey the conceptions deriving from his own
experiences, acknowledging that his concepts are his own reactions to the
surround of phenomena in which he exists. He
is a mystic. Individuals are often
victimized by the thoughts of others; the philosopher is the Good Samaritan who
stands up for the interior life of every individual. He creates, using the
imagery of Père Teilhard, the beneficent noosphere
in which the life of the mind can develop as it can and should.
Voltaire commented that no army can stop an idea whose
time has come, but Emerson was more accurate when he said beware when the great
God lets loose a thinker upon the planet (Circles).
The time of an idea arrives because the powerful mind of a human being has
stimulated its emergence in the minds of others. It might have been better to
say that no army can destroy an idea once it has been brought into existence by
one seized with the spirit of philosophy.
A necessary faith of the philosopher is that someone
else, not all but someone, can feel and think what he feels and thinks. The
philosopher is intoxicated with the idea that he has a spiritual brother
somewhere in the world. It is only when this intoxication proceeds to
forgetfulness of self that he becomes an absurd figure. Much worse than this
forgetfulness, however, is loss of faith in his vision. The spiritual
imperative for philosophers is to act as if their spiritual perceptions can be perceived by someone else. If this
faith flags, as it apparently did in the case of Nietzsche, the philosopher zugrunde geht (he perishes).
All art forms have their special type of experience that
they offer. The art of the novel is the portrayal of characters; it is
axiomatic that the story of a great novel must remain secondary to its
characters. A poet transforms his inner state into the rhythms and imagery of
his language. The experiences offered by theater, musical, and visual arts are
self-evident. There are historical changes in receptivity of styles of
expression. For example, long narrative poems and poetry as philosophy went out
of fashion long ago—as Robinson Jeffers discovered to his chagrin. However, the
interesting prose poem Das Energi
(sic) by Paul Williams (1978) might have been a forerunner of a swing back to
Lucretius’ use of poetry as a philosophical vehicle. So far, this has not
happened.
Philosophical expression as a literary art form has not entered the consciousness of the
contemporary public. It is by his ability to present his feeling-generated
ideas that the philosopher must be judged, not by his journalistic abilities or
scholarly expertise. Ideas even more than emotions are capable of affecting an
individual because they can take root and grow in his mind. Kierkegaard and
Nietzsche, the two modern philosophers who have had the greatest impact on
western culture, although they were learned, were quite unscholarly, often
exhibiting incoherent prose styles, and were not understood at first by many
well-educated readers. However, they were artists in philosophy who believed
that expression of their feelings took precedence over all other considerations
and, ultimately, their thoughts took hold. One should be suspicious of a
philosopher whose ideas become quickly popular—it is not likely he is
expressing his unique state of mind.
Philosophy as an art form is
found elsewhere besides within western culture. It is evident that the forest
thinkers of the Vedic world of India had mastered the art of philosophy. One
must peer between lines of the awkward translations of Sanskrit into English to
discover the force and liveliness of the ancient Indian philosophers. The
Upanishads were the repository of Vedic wisdom, and, unlike much ancient Greek
philosophy, have been carefully preserved and reverenced up to the present
time. A fine contemporary means of gaining access to the Hindu world of long
ago is to view the remains of Hindu erotic temple art. Those Hindus were people
of breadth and depth who understood the relationship of eroticism to wisdom!
But like the ancient Greeks, the Vedic wise men are long gone, along with the
world that produced them. India now eagerly snaps up the technology of the west
and exports gurus in exchange.
~ ~ ~
Professors and scholars in
the university world of philosophy are in the habit of demanding detailed
documentation of scholarly credentials as a requirement for publication in
philosophy. This is a characteristic of all areas in which scholarly
specialists form a guild. It is a means of maintaining control over their
areas. But few creative personalities have the inclination to subject
themselves to guild control. Scholars reject the idea that the ‘unscholarly’
can express themselves philosophically in a manner that deserves serious
consideration. This is a dog in the manger attitude since ‘philosophers’ formed
by scholarship are unable themselves to create philosophy. Their skills are
appropriate for historical research or cognitive science but are of little
value in an independent art form like philosophy. The academic monopoly of
western philosophy has resulted in its virtual disappearance as a vital form of
expression.
The creation of philosophical writing is not like
building an architectural monument, it is more like composing a sonata; there
are threads to pursue and themes to work out but they are intermingled, not
carved out separately. The reader needs to expand the capacities of his
receptive self to follow the expressions of a philosopher; one cannot read
authentic philosophy without this expansion any more than one can appreciate
Bach without some experience of classical music. Philosophers do not
systematically proceed from one foundation stone to another in laying out the
‘truth’. The systematic philosophers have deceived their readers since they
have provided logical structures in which the human feelings of the philosopher
are no longer discernable. This discovery forms the basis of Kierkegaard’s scathing
criticisms of Hegel. The same kind of objection applies even more to the
theologians—Augustine, Aquinas, Luther, and others of a similar ilk. They all
bring their own religious prejudices into the philosophical arena, claiming to
be the recipient of metaphysical revelations that underpin their own
philosophies. In my judgment, they are harmful figures who have impeded
philosophical development and constricted the minds of those who trusted them.
The philosopher artist does not follow the sequential steps
of logical analysis aiming toward scientific truth. He expresses himself
according to a different tempo; here, there, there, here. It is the tempo of
the tides rather than that of Kant. Each position in his work is existential,
not sequential. Critics who find this approach disorganized, unscholarly, or
unhistorical should turn to scholarship or history for their field of activity.
However, a reader should remember that an exposition claiming to be
philosophical that does not project the interior state of the philosopher is
like a caress not motivated by love; it leaves one with the unpleasant sense of
having been misused by the caresser.
As for science, it is the plumbing of humanity. As such,
it deserves greater or lesser attention according to one’s interest in
plumbing. Societies are generally not habitable without plumbing of some sort.
Nonetheless, few will disagree that when a society gives all its energies to
the plumbing, it seems hardly worth the effort to maintain it. Paraphrasing an
assertion of the young George Lukacs, “Science offers us facts and
relationships between facts, but art and philosophy offers us souls and
destinies.” That Lukacs later went on to throw in his destiny with scientific
Marxism does not take away from the depth of his youthful insight. Philosophers
do not teach facts and their relationships; they provide a linguistic link to
their own inner feelings and intuitions.
~ ~ ~
I think it important that a
philosopher guard against writing too much; gigantic philosophical tomes are
like the Pyramids of Egypt—monuments whose impact derives from their size
rather than their substance. The length of many contemporary books tends to be
based on commercial advantage instead of the writer’s instincts. If a
philosophical book is too long, the spiritual blood of the philosopher is
drained before the book is completed. Nietzsche’s Untimely Reflections are ideal lengths for works of philosophy;
later as Nietzsche grew shriller, his books proliferated until finally there
was nothing left of the exhausted philosopher.
The capacity to stop writing is fully as important as the
art of starting. Books of historical analysis may go on for thousands of pages;
extreme examples are provided by Spengler and Toynbee. This is impossible for
philosophy that is the outcome of the interior state of a philosopher. Kierkegaard’s
and Nietzsche’s short works are their best in my opinion because they reflect
the natural movements of their minds and one does not sense that either of them
struggled to complete them. On the other hand, Concluding Unscientific Postscript and Thus Spoke Zarathustra may have unduly stressed their writers.
~ ~ ~
The philosopher who writes
with the requirements of success in the market place is akin to a lover who
woos for the purpose of sexual intercourse. Both are reprehensible since they
are not straightforward in their expressions. One promises wisdom, the other
promises love, but both only desire conquest. No societal or sexual success is
worth the deformation of personality caused by deceitfulness. Socrates
maintained that the health of the soul is dependent upon cultivation of
truthfulness. It is difficult to think of a worse deception than dishonesty of
personal expression. It is in direct opposition to the highest human ideal,
that of transmission of one’s own inner state to other individuals. If a person
lies in personal expression, literary or otherwise, he degrades himself and
sets the stage for his spiritual oblivion.
However, regardless of the long decline of traditional
philosophy, the desire to find meaning in feelings has found alternative ways
of expression. Poets like Robinson Jeffers, Gary Snyder, Paul Williams, and
Eliot Schain have sought deeper meanings in their writings. The antique belief
that the expressions of philosophers ought to be concordant with the totality
of their lives, a belief long ignored by bourgeois professors, is being
rediscovered through simpler ways of living, as exemplified by the life and
writings of Wendell Berry. It has become clear that life’s fulfillment cannot
be extracted from politico-economic-scientific solutions or from superannuated
religions that only give lip service to their original visions. No amount of
logical thinking or dogma imposed from without can substitute for the force of
individual feelings from which philosophy evolved as an art form.
~ ~ ~
The philosopher as an
expressive artist lives much of his life removed from the milieu of societal
living. It is not that he retires from the world out of disdain for it; in
fact, the philosopher is a person who intensely responds to the world. It is
rather because he alters his personality so that it functions expressively
instead of interactively. The alteration cannot be a superficial one—there is
nothing as unrewarding as a superficial philosopher—but must reach into the
depths of his being and involve his total life’s energies. The effort to
function expressively and yet maintain a societal life with relationships and
all that goes with them produces a great strain on his personality. This is why
philosophers seek solitude and are prone to nervous breakdowns as was both
pointed out and exemplified by Friedrich Nietzsche.
Yet one cannot create philosophy in a state of complete
isolation. One may find God in a cave or on a mountain peak but if the philosopher
wishes to experience the world as it is, then he must reach out to other
individuals—even if only to one other person. Dostoevsky wrote that at least
one profound relationship is necessary to justify one’s presence on earth. More
than that is probably beyond the abilities of most philosophers. The Russian
thinker also famously wrote in his novel The
Idiot, “Beauty will save the world.” He ought to have said art instead of beauty.
Published in: Confrontation, 122, 2017, pp. 142-160. (A
shorter version appears in Philosophy
Pathways, 2016.)